Minggu, 17 Oktober 2010

NOAH AND THE SPACESHIP

Alexandre Meinesz, How Life Began—Evolution’s Three Geneses
translated by Daniel Simberloff. The University of Chicago Press,
Chicago
Ellen Clarke
Received: 9 February 2009 / Accepted: 9 February 2009 / Published online: 22 February 2009
Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009
Abstract
and Christians, but Alexandre Meinesz’s recent book
provide a reconciliation between the two. Here I review his somewhat unorthodox
perspective on major transitions, alien origins and the meaning of life, with a critical
focus on his account of the generation of multicellularity.
Evolution has increasingly become a topic of conflict between scientistsHow Life Began aims to
Keywords
Meinesz is already known as a popular science author for his work
Christianity Major transitions PanspermiaKiller Algae
(
further away from his home territory in this book which attempts the much grander
task of assimilating biology, history and philosophy into the sort of text that would
not look out of place on the bookshelf at Sunday school. This is evolution for the
religious, the book of Genesis rewritten for the modern world. It combines personal
reflections on art with summaries of the latest discoveries in molecular biology and
paleoecology to offer a uniquely spiritual perspective on cutting edge science.
Meinesz claims there have been three distinct geneses or creations in
evolutionary history. One is the origin of bacteria (about which he says surprisingly
little, save that it did not happen on earth). One is the origin by symbiosis of the
eukaryotes—which is actually a rather heterogeneous collection of separate
transitions, including the origins of the nucleus and of sex, supposedly unified by
the common mechanism of symbiosis. The third and last is the origin of
multicellularity. It is not entirely clear what these three ‘events’ have in common,
that could distinguish them from many other candidate transitions such as the origin
of life, the origin of chromosomes, the origin of cell walls, the origin of language, or
1999) about the dangerous spread of non-native algae. As a phycologist he is a little
E. Clarke (
Philosophy Department, University of Bristol, 9 Woodland Road, Bristol BS8 1TB, UK
e-mail: ec5035@bris.ac.uk
&)
123
Biol Philos (2009) 24:725–734
DOI 10.1007/s10539-009-9157-y
the origin of superorganisms or colonies. He distinguishes four fundamental forces
or motors of evolution—mutation, sexual recombination, natural selection by the
environment and mass extinctions or cataclysms. He emphasizes contingency in
evolution, as well as union—the alliances and aggregations that have made the
evolution of complex life possible. Like Gould (and McShea) his emphasis is on a
long term paleontological view of evolution which emphasizes the success and
longevity of bacteria, in contrast to a more progressive or adaptationist view.
Some highlights are worth mentioning—chapter three is devoted to bacteria, in
fact it’s a tribute to them. We learn about their astonishing super-powers, their
incredible diversity and resilience, their unsurpassed dominance in terms of
numbers and longevity on the planet, as well as their indispensability to all other
forms of life. Chapter six looks at controversies in the history of biology regarding
large scale trends and the tempo of evolution with an impressively accessible
treatment of the epistemological problems that paleoecologists face. He explains
how different sources of evidence are collected and combined to try to reconstruct
the history of life, and how the limitations of these sources of evidence constrain
and possibly bias that picture. There is lots of science here—real photos of
specimens and details about dates, combined in a way that lets the reader feel what
it must be like to be at the forefront of science. Chapter nine contains the high point
of the book—the issue of the so-called sixth mass extinction. Here he manages the
difficult task of stirring your passion on an issue that is so well-rehearsed in these
sorts of books that it is difficult to write about without sounding like you’ve simply
copied it all down from some ecological holy book. Yet Meinesz manages to
breathe new life into the topic.
How Life Began
much history of science as science, with a good deal of philosophy thrown in as
well, which is a huge amount of ground to cover in just one book. He covers most of
the major debates in recent evolutionary biology and parts of the work are dense and
rich, but other times things are rushed over so fast that I wonder what the lay reader
would really have gleaned from it. The book opens with a motif that runs throughout
the work—a description of a painting of Antoni van Leeuwenhoek by Vermeer,
which Meinesz uses as an illustration of science as he claims it ought to be done—
with one’s attention turned to the infinite and the mysterious but with one’s feet
placed firmly on the ground. All chapters open with some sort of concrete setting, a
personal anecdote or a distant memory recalled, demonstrating the author’s
determination that he does not sound like a distant inaccessible scholar lecturing
from his ivory tower. Meinesz is keen to reassure the reader that his great intellect
does not preclude him from reaching out to mere mortals.
Largely Meinesz’ efforts to inject his story with spiritual and artistic flourishes
left me cold. I found them clumsy and patronising at best. Maybe there are issues of
translation here, or maybe just turns of phrase that only a philosopher would object
to—for example, he claims that the origin of life
(Meinesz
want to alienate half his readership by interrupting his chapter on bacteria to muse
on the thought of a ‘‘beautiful woman with bare breasts’’ (Meinesz
Some chapters feel more like random collections of essays than coherent pieces of a
would be called a work of popular science, although it is asentails the origin of the first cells2008, p. 23). At his worst he is arrogant and chauvinistic—why does he2008, p. 65)?
726 E. Clarke
123
larger story, and some of it is downright repetitive although his writing is at its
strongest in the most scientific parts, where you feel that he benefits from letting go
of his stiflingly self-conscious desire to sound profound.
Three features of this book make it stand out from the crowd of other books on
the history of life, such as Dawkins’
Szathmary’s
mention). Firstly, panspermia. Although this book is entitled ‘
does not actually treat the origins of life at all, it merely discusses the arrival of life
on earth. Secondly, the emphasis on union—symbioses and endosymbioses.
Meinesz claims that these kinds of relationships represent a revolution, a schism,
under-represented in evolutionary theory and a departure from Darwinian evolution.
Thirdly, and most conspicuously, religion. This is a self-consciously spiritual work
of popular science which some might find jarring. You cannot ignore the religious
content in this book, nor easily separate it from the scientific—in fact a discussion of
the relationship between evolution and Christianity comprises the heart of several
chapters. I’ll discuss all these departures, as well as carrying out a critical
examination of his treatment of one of the more conventional topics—the transition
to multicellularity.
Ancestor’s Tale or Maynard Smith andMajor Transitions in Evolution (which Meinesz conspicuously fails toHow Life Began’ it
Panspermia (or more properly, exogenesis)
Meinesz devotes a whole chapter to defending the theory that life originated on an
alien planet before seeding earth and it is evidently one of his favourite axes to grind
(although I struggled to find further work on it by him). It is a passionate defence,
using various plausibility arguments as well as giving an impressively clear account
of some fairly convoluted evidence. Meinesz presents evidence from Friedmann
showing that the meteorite ALH84001 dated to around 4.5 bya (and originating on
Mars) contains traces of compounds (magnetite chains) usually only formed by
bacteria. Supporting evidence suggests that there is a very low possibility that such
compounds were formed in abiotic reactions such as mineralization especially since
they were found aligned into perfect ‘necklaces’ just as in our cells. He further argues
against the possibility of contamination of the meteor or samples. Meinesz
acknowledges widespread controversy as to the veracity of these claims, but
attributes it to personal jealousy and conservatism. What mainstream science would
have to gain by sidelining such evidence is not spelt out. This bit reads as a
fascinating insight into the lives (and political battles) of scientists and it would add
up into a reasonable hypothesis
at least an awareness of the typical response of most evolutionists to panspermia
theory. Meinesz offers no answer to the ‘So what?’ problem. What difference does it
make? Most evolutionists find panspermia a hypothesis with limited appeal, simply
because it seems to want to side step the mysteries that really get evolutionists going,
by removing them to a more distant location. Panspermia per se does not solve the
problem of how life originated, it simply extends the available time frame and
environment. Meinesz chooses not, after all, to discuss hypotheses about how life
began at all and, like Will Wright’s computer game ‘Spore,’ simply starts at bacteria.
if it was not so obviously one-sided and if he showed
Noah and the spaceship 727
123
Unions
Meinesz intends his work to emphasize the power of an oft-neglected force in
evolution—symbiosis. French biology since Portier has tended to pay more
attention to unions in biology than have the anglo-american traditions (see Sapp
1994
and that tradition is continued in this most patriotic of books. We are presented with
the Elysia sea slug, hero of Meinesz’ previous book
manner in which lineages can borrow traits from one another by symbiosis. The slug
apparently preys on Caulerpa, a tropical alga, and ingests the alga’s cytoplasm
without digesting its chloroplasts. It then deposits the chloroplasts under the surface
of its skin where it uses them to produce energy just like a plant ordinarily does. It is
a slug that photosynthesizes. Meinesz tells the tale well and inserts it within a larger
piece on symbioses and the role they have played in major transitions in evolution.
He draws a direct analogy between the sea slug using stolen chloroplasts, and
prokaryotes using engulfed mitochondria to become the first eukaryotes in
Margulis’ endosymbiosis theory.
It is great that Meinesz puts so much emphasis on this defining kind of union in
evolutionary history, and he is honest here in presenting competing hypotheses and
emphasizing the speculative nature of some of the claims. The somewhat dense
material is also aided tremendously by his cheerful little cartoon storyboards. Yet
the details do not all come through crystal clear, and at times this chapter is
muddled, partly because there is just too much in it. For example, the role of
symbioses more generally in evolution is left unclear, so that it seems
indistinguishable from co-evolution, and the text gets muddied up by non-precise
use of terms like ‘individual’ and ‘partner’ which is common but damaging to a
discussion of endosymbiosis. I also take issue with the extent to which Meinesz
wants to claim that symbiosis is a process different in kind from Darwinian
evolution. He declares it a revolution and a new genesis. But these are not
equivalent. Evolutionary transitions in individuality such as the origin of eukaryotes
and of multicellulars do indeed comprise new geneses in that they create objects at
new higher levels of selection, but they are generally perceived as occurring due to
standard Darwinian processes of variation and selection. Symbiosis may count as a
different source of variation than mutation, especially if we insist that not all new
behaviours have genetic mutations underpinning them, but so does lateral gene
transfer, polyploidy and sex. It is true that symbiosis has often not been given a
sufficiently important place in the history of life, but the optimal way to redress this
balance is not to cry revolution.
Many evolutionary histories restrict their examination of aggregations to the
rather prejudicially named ‘problem’ of altruism. The free-rider problem sees no
mention at all within this book. Instead alliances are depicted as unproblematically
synergistic relationships, illustrated with cartoon amoeba smiling even as they
ingest one another.
It is true that even after Margulis’ initially astonishing hypotheses have been
incorporated into mainstream orthodoxy, many biologists still view symbiosis as the
exception to the norm. But would moving symbiosis closer to the spotlight in
for a history), with their greater attention to individuals and to competition,Killer Algae, to illustrate the
728 E. Clarke
123
evolutionary writing really constitute the revolution that Meinesz heralds? Is
symbiosis at odds with the neo-Darwinian synthesis? As is common what we have
here is a difference of emphasis, presented as a difference in kind. It is true that
mainstream accounts of evolution focus on the accumulation and natural selection
of mutations. The question we must ask, however, is whether symbiosis constitutes
a phenomenon that contradicts, extends, or fits neatly within, this description. Most
authors would say that while symbiosis may constitute an evolutionary mechanism
of organism construction in addition to the selection of mutation, it does
not
undermine or contradict traditional Darwinian selection. The problem is that the
theoretical battle fought between adherents of cooperation and mutualism and of
competition and survival of the fittest, is that the two sides were often
misrepresented as sentimental utopians, on one side, and hard-headed realists on
the other. The mundane truth acceptable to all is that natural selection will favour
alliance whenever it offers synergistic benefits that cannot be acquired alone. The
war of appropriate emphasis then turns on the empirical question of how often such
benefits exist, and the answer increasingly looks to be: a lot. To this extent then
Meinesz can be applauded for seeking to secure a more central position for
symbiosis within evolutionary theory, but I fall short of calling such a change a
‘revolution.’
Religion
You cannot escape the religion in this book. Not only does Meinesz constantly refer
to it, but several chapters are specifically dedicated to evaluating science in the light
of belief and vice versa. One might accuse Meinesz of wanting to rewrite
Ancestor’s Tale
life accessible and exciting for non-scientists, but without the atheistic vitriol for
which Dawkins has become famous. It is not a bad ambition, as I’m sure Dawkins’
name on the cover is enough to prevent many people who would benefit from it
from even opening
evolutionary theory as something compatible with religion and spiritualism, without
shrinking from the actual hard science. Unfortunately, he lacks Dawkins’ effortless
capacity for bringing science to vivid and colourful life in the mind of the reader. I
am happy to allow that I am not the believing layman at whom this work is aimed
but I still feel it is a shame that scientists feel the need to muddy their work by
associating it with all this metaphysical stuff on which they are not qualified to
pronounce.
Meinesz sets the tone of the book in chapter one when he talks about a friend’s
determination to retain ownership of land in which some of the oldest prehistoric
cave paintings are found. It is a metaphor perhaps for our common ownership of our
past, for Meinesz goes on to discuss the various creation myths and tries to
emphasize that whatever your beliefs, our past is a shared truth to which all of us
remain connected. He mixes palaeontology with bible stories in a way designed to
emphasize our fascination with our origins. He mostly presents the bible stories as
just stories, while the palaeontology is fact, but he demurs sufficiently to leave room
Thefor theists. Like Dawkins he wants to make the deep of history ofThe Ancestor’s Tale. Meinesz, a Catholic, wants to present
Noah and the spaceship 729
123
for people not to feel contradicted. He even presents the standard Catholic line about
God inserting the soul at some critical moment in evolution, by saying ‘‘Present-day
knowledge would surely have led the authors of Genesis to reserve for God alone
the impulse to create the soul’’ (Meinesz
He does not call it science, but he mixes his religion in with his science sufficiently
closely that only prior knowledge allows the reader to easily tell them apart.
Meinesz spends a long time evaluating evidence for a large scale flood that could
have served as the inspiration for the biblical story of Noah and the Ark, about
which I was tempted to say ‘who cares’ leaving the reader to fill in the obvious
answer. But maybe that’s mean, maybe even ‘non-believers’ can find interest in the
capacity that science gives us to explore the origins of these undeniably important
old myths.
Contingency is the issue that Meinesz keeps coming back to because he seems to
view it as presenting the biggest threat to a religious thought. He settles for Gould’s
line that if we reran the tape of evolution, we would see a radically different
outcome, and asks how much this non-teleological worldview threatens the way in
which theists view the ‘meaning of life’. Meinesz also adopts Gould’s other position
about science and religion being NOMA (non overlapping distinct magisteria;
Meinesz
two ‘Magisteria’ and keep out of metaphysical debates that are best left to theists
(even if he fails to take this particular piece of advice himself). So while the
scientific Magisteria rule that evolution is fundamentally contingent and not goaldirected,
this has no bearing on the separate kinds of arguments that the spiritual
magisterial are going to offer regarding mankind’s purpose in life, or what we can
expect to happen after we die. He criticises intelligent design hypotheses for failing
to distinguish these domains, for letting the scientific picture be dictated to by
religion. He claims that the religious or spiritual domain ought to let science proceed
by its own lights without intruding on or feeling threatened by its discoveries.
Most people simply reject this proposed bifurcation. Atheists reject the idea that
the moral domain is only accessible by believers, while theists probably resent the
idea of having to survive on science’s leftovers. Meinesz puts the religious domain
into a subservient relationship with science that many theists would, I imagine, find
hard to accept. The onus is on religious leaders to adjust their views as science
makes new discoveries, not vice versa. Science and religion are not non-overlapping
domains because we do not know what science will discover in the future so we do
not yet have a properly delineated scientific domain. If this is the case then it is
impossible for religion to be sure it does not pronounce on something which science
will later contradict. Religion is condemned to play second fiddle, playing catch up.
Meinesz certainly is no apologist for creationists, and emphasizes that the bible is
just plain wrong about lots of things and that life really is just ‘‘the result of a long,
pitiless, random struggle for survival in the face of incessant arbitrary decapitations’’
(Meinesz
atheism, just reinterpretation of scripture. ‘‘Ancient, divine messages can be adapted
to modern knowledge.’’ I’m really one of those atheists who would prefer ‘the
faithful’ to be proper full blooded believers or not at all. Talking about the need to
reinterpret religious texts while simultaneously asserting their truth and divinity
2008, p. 17). It is unsubtle word-weaselry.2008, p. 116) and he states that scientists should stick to their half of the2008, p. 193). Yet he does not think this necessitates conversion to
730 E. Clarke
123
seems like a textbook recipe for trouble: at least literalists have a limited number of
excuses at their disposal. However, Meinesz does not present his religious views as
justifying or excusing anything. Ultimately he is trying to show that believing in
evolution does not force a person to become a non-believer. And he is probably
right. Nonetheless, his religiosity is bound to raise the hackles of
anyone
accustomed to finding wonderment in nature without having to overlay it with a
greasy coat of magical realism.
Origins of multicellularity
The move to multicellularity is a new genesis because, like Lego pieces, it provides
a new and unlimited way of constructing novel organisms by the addition of
different combinations of pieces in different ways. The creative power of
multicellularity lies in its modularity. Organisms can be created in cumulative
stages, where each stage is robust and can be added to without limit. Meinesz claims
that the move to colonial living was presaged by a change in life style—some
organisms left the surface waters of the oceans and settled on narrow ledges of
continental shelf, where the water is shallow enough that plenty of sunlight filters
through. Here they faced a whole different set of ecological challenges—no longer
required to subfloat, they in fact secured advantage by anchoring themselves to the
floor of their hospitable new home.
Much of this chapter is spent debating a single question—was the transition to
multicellularity a simple case of responding adaptively to a changed environmental
circumstances—i.e., to living on a shallow ledge (the ‘‘convergent evolution
hypothesis’’). Or did the move from open water simply allow a pre-existing capacity
to develop and thrive where the previous environment did not favour it (the ‘‘shared
software hypothesis’’). Meinesz places a lot of importance on comparing these
hypotheses. But what turns on whether those mutations happened before of after the
change in habitat? Even if multicellularity is a new life history trait that appeared in
response to a change of habitat, that trait was made possible by an underlying
genetic architecture (combined of course with various other epigenetic and
environmental conditions). Probably a mutation, or a series of mutations, had to
happen to that architecture before multicellularity was available as a strategy. There
are a few reasons why Meinesz thinks it is important to distinguish between the rival
hypotheses.
Firstly, Meinesz sees the existence of multicellularity in multiple distinct
lineages, but not all lineages, as a fact in need of explanation. A trait such as flying
is present across multiple lineages, including birds and mammals. We say that this
trait is analogous, or has appeared by convergent evolution, because the evolution of
flight in bats took place long after the bat lineage separated from the bird lineage.
On the other hand, we say that possession of a vertebra is a homologous trait across
vertebrates because all vertebrates descend from a common ancestor that had a
vertebra. Meinesz thinks the existence of underlying homologous genetic architecture
provides this explanation, but analogy does not, because if multicellularity was
an analogous trait in distinct lineages then we should expect to find it in
all lineages
Noah and the spaceship 731
123
that have sessile lifestyles. Only the ‘shared software’ hypothesis can explain why
some lineages have not made the transition to multicellularity. This is too strong,
because many things that are evolutionary possibilities fail to happen. Dolphins and
sharks have a convergently evolved aquiline body form that helps them swim
efficiently in water, yet there are no fully aquatic marsupials. However, if the
various lineages diverged before any of them had acquired the mutation necessary
for multicellularity, then we have to suppose that the multicellular lineages all
acquired the necessary mutation independently, which Meinesz seems to think is
less attractive on the grounds of parsimony.
Another reason Meinesz has for advocating the shared software hypothesis is that
offers him a route to coherence with his preferred explanation for the appearance of
life on earth—panspermia. If some but not all organismal lineages possess some sort
of necessary genetic precursor to multicellularity, then Meinesz can say that those
lineages descended from different strains of alien bacteria.
Lastly, it seems that Meinesz prefers the shared software hypothesis because it
allows him to give a scientific explanation that is compatible with a theistic need for
the evolution of man to be inevitable. Meinesz claims that if multicellularity is the
result of some shared software, then ‘‘organisms were pre-programmed to become
multicellular when they became sedentary’’ (164) and multicellularity is a
deterministic phenomenon.
Meinesz wants to believe that multicellularity evolved simultaneously across all
lineages and only after the move to sedentary living, and that examples of
multicellular organisms achieved their multicellular status via a single common
mutation or set of mutations. Yet the most up to date evidence suggests that
multicellularity appeared early and repeatedly, because of a confluence of
environmental, ecological and genetic factors. In a recent review, Rokas
2008
claims that multicellularity is a heterogeneous trait across different lineages but that
it first appeared in filamentous cyanobacteria, appearing in the fossil record 2.5–
2.1 bya. Multicellular eukaryotes appeared soon after the appearance of eukaryotes,
around 1.2 bya, with complex forms appearing 1.0–0.4 bya. Volvocine algae
represent the most recent invention of multicellularity, around 0.05 bya. It is
obvious therefore that complex multicellularity appeared neither rapidly nor
simultaneously an all phyla. Furthermore, Rokas says that ‘‘Not all instantiations of
multicellularity are the same, and they do differ in important details’’ (Rokas
p. 239). For example, multicellularity in volvox likely evolved after incomplete
separation after cell division, whereas in Dictyostelium it is a result of aggregation.
‘‘Thus any expectation that gene families participating in cell adhesion in the two
lineages would show similar trends would likely be unfounded’’ (Rokas
239). It is now known that Dictyostelium achieve multicellularity using a distinct
array of genetic software from the fungi, plants and animals (Williams et al.
Research done on Volvocine algae also shows that volvocale multicellularity
differs from metazoan multicellularity precisely because they are underpinned by
distinct genotype–phenotype map structures. V. carteri achieve multicellularity
using a gene RegA to conditionally inhibit chloroplast production in some of their
cells. These cells are then prevented from growing to the size which triggers mitosis,
and so are restricted to somatic functions throughout the lifetime of the group. This
2008,2008, p.2005).
732 E. Clarke
123
rather crude way of achieving a division of labour prevents V. carteri from
developing multiple cell types and is offered as an explanation for why the
volvocale transition to multicellularity has not been followed by an explosion of
diversity, as in metazoan lineages (Nedelcu and Michod
metazoans have achieved multicellularity using a more complex series of mutations
at the cellular level so that different sizes of cell can be produced, and mitosis can be
controlled by independent factors such as cell signalling. The key to the hypothesis
is an explanation for
did not. The answer lies in a peculiarity of volvocine mitosis. While most metazoan
cells divide by binary fission, with one cell splitting to produce two, volvocales have
multiple fission. Binary fission allows you to incrementally increase cell size, for
example. Multiple fission means that mitosis of an adult cell reproduces a whole
multicellular individual.
We can surely imagine similar sorts of constraints might block the possibility of
multicellularity altogether in some lineages, refuting Meinesz’ conjecture that only
a shared software hypothesis could explain the absence of multicellularity in these
lineages. On the other hand it has been found that most of the genetic toolkit
necessary for multicellularity in metazoan lineages is also present in unicellular
ancestors. Genes have mostly been co-opted rather than gained anew, though they
have often dramatically increased in number or gained new functions. Some
components, however, do seem to be genuinely novel innovations. The main genetic
changes concern genes responsible for regulating cell differentiation, cell-cell
signalling pathways and cell adhesion. In the evolution of animal multicellularity,
‘‘gene machinery predated but was co-opted for multicellularity in the time
antecedent to the transition’’ (Rokas
we find the most up to date consensus is that the whole bilaterian clade—i.e., all the
different animal phyla that evolved from a common sponge or cnidarian ancestor—
share a common genetic toolkit, including ancient hox gene clusters. Geneticists
think that duplications and modifications (tinkering) of these very old genes
underpin all of the modern body plans. The closest relatives of the bilaterians, the
cnidarians and sponges, show intermediate forms of multicellularity/coloniality and
a range of sessile and motile lifestyles.
Multicellularity is a homologous trait in some respects, and an analogous trait in
others. It
(ecological and environmental) and intrinsic (genetic) factors in the origin of animal
multicellularity, but this does not amount to the dichotomy that Meinesz portrays.
The evidence therefore says that to some extent the software did predate the
transition (within this lineage) but to some extent new mutations were needed, as
well as much gene duplication and cooption of function. Meinesz may be
overplaying the importance of analogy versus homology here—the matter turns on
common ancestry, which is a matter of degree (Griffiths
alternative developmental view of homology then multicellularity probably is not a
candidate homologue at all). All phyla have a common ancestor (probably, because
they all use the same DNA code) and homology and homoplasy are not sides of a
dichotomy but ends of a continuum, separated by varying degrees of modification,
reflecting deep or more recent ancestry (see Hall
2003, 2006). Otherwhy volvox ran up against these constraints, when other phylas2008, p. 246). In fact if we look to the literatureis interesting to ask what was the relative contribution of extrinsic2007 denies this, but on the2007). The final question then is
Noah and the spaceship 733
123
why Meinesz or anyone else should believe that securing one end or other of this
continuum as the explanation for a trait has any bearing at all on the meaning of
life? Homology looks a long way away from the kind of inevitability that theists
really seek.
The epilogue that ends
Scientists, Meinesz declares, must leave their ivory towers and face the responsibilities
of dissemination and communication of knowledge. Biologists, in
particular, have a duty to guarantee a widespread appreciation of the beauty and
fragility of the world we live in. Whether or not I believe in life after death, I agree
that biologists have a special part to play in ensuring that there is life after
tomorrow.
How Life Began serves primarily as a call to arms.
References
Griffiths PE (2007) The phenomena of homology. Biol Philos 22:643–658. doi:
9090-x
10.1007/s10539-007-
Hall BK (2007) Homoplasy and homology: dichotomy or continuum? J Hum Evol 52(5):473–479
Meinesz A (1999) Killer algae. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Meinesz A (2008) How life began: evolution’s three geneses. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Nedelcu A, Michod RE (2003) Evolvability, modularity, and individuality during the transition to
multicellularity in volvocalean green algae. In: Schlosser G, Wagner G (eds) Modularity in
development and evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Nedelcu A, Michod RE (2006) The evolutionary origin of an altruistic gene. Mol Biol Evol 23(8):
1460–1464
Rokas A (2008) The origins of multicellularity and the early history of the genetic toolkit for animal
development. Annu Rev Genet 42:235–251. doi:
10.1146/annurev.genet.42.110807.091513
Sapp J (1994) Evolution by association—a history of symbiosis. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Williams J, Noegel A, Eichinger L (2005) Manifestations of multicellularity—dictyostelium reports in.
Trends Genet 21:392–398. doi:
10.1016/j.tig.2005.05.002
734 E. Clarke
123

Noah and the spaceship: evolution for twenty-first
century christians

Tidak ada komentar:

Posting Komentar